CHAPTER X Aesthetic and Ethical Culture
THE idea of culture begins to define itself for us a little more clearly, or at least it has put away from it in a clear contrast its natural opposites. The unmental, the purely physical life is very obviously its opposite, it is barbarism; the unintellectualised vital, the crude economic or the grossly domestic life which looks only to money-getting, the procreation of a family and its maintenance, are equally its opposites; they are another and even uglier barbarism. We agree to regard the individual who is dominated by them and has no thought of higher things as an uncultured and undeveloped human being, a prolongation of the savage, essentially a barbarian even if he lives in a civilised nation and in a society which has arrived at the general idea and at some ordered practice of culture and refinement. The societies or nations which bear this stamp we agree to call barbarous or semi-barbarous. Even when a nation or an age has developed within itself knowledge and science and arts, but still in its general outlook, its habits of life and thought is content to be governed not by knowledge and truth and beauty and high ideals of living, but by the gross vital, commercial, economic view of existence, we say that that nation or age may be civilised in a sense, but for all its abundant or even redundant appliances and apparatus of civilisation it is not the realisation or the promise of a cultured humanity. Therefore upon even the European civilisation of the nineteenth century with all its triumphant and teeming production, its great developments of science, its achievement in the works of the intellect we pass a certain condemnation, because it has turned all these things to commercialism and to gross uses of vitalistic success. We say of it that this was not the perfection to which humanity ought to aspire and that this trend travels away from and not towards the higher curve of human evolution. It must be our definite verdict Page – 84 upon it that it was inferior as an age of culture to
ancient Athens, to Italy of the Renascence, to ancient or classical India. For
great as might be the deficiencies of social organisation in those eras and
though their range of scientific knowledge and material achievement was
immensely inferior, yet they were more advanced in the art of life, knew better
its object and aimed more powerfully at some clear ideal of human perfection. Page – 85 for character and high ethical ideals and a large human
action, not to be governed by our lower or our average mentality but by truth
and beauty and the self-ruling will is the ideal of a true culture and the
beginning of an accomplished humanity;
1 The epithet is needed, for European Christianity has been something different, even at its best of another temperament, Latinised, Graecised, Celticised or else only a rough Teutonic imitation of the old-world Hebraism. Page – 86 able extent in the light of its master idea of beauty;
the good was to its instinct largely the becoming and the beautiful. In
philosophy itself it succeeded in arriving at the conception of the Divine as
Beauty, a truth ‘which the metaphysician very readily misses and impoverishes
his thought by missing it. But still, striking as is this great historical
contrast and powerful as were its results on European culture, we have to go
beyond its outward manifestation if we would understand in its source this
psycho- logical opposition. Page – 87 by its attractive appeals to the passions and emotions
destructive of a high and strict self-control. He sees that it is hedonistic
and he finds that the hedonistic impulse is non-moral and often immoral. It is
difficult for him to see how the indulgence of the aesthetic impulse beyond a
very narrow and carefully guarded limit can be combined with a strict ethical
life. He evolves the puritan who objects to pleasure on principle; not only in
his extremes – and a predominant impulse tends to become absorbing and leads
towards extremes – but in the core of his temperament he remains fundamentally
the puritan. The misunderstanding between these two sides of our nature is an
inevitable circumstance of our human growth which must try them to their
fullest separate possibilities and experiment in extremes in order that it may
understand the whole range of its capacities. Page – 88 though it influences them all; it is sui generis and must be treated
separately. To get at real, if not always quite pure examples of the type we
must go back a little farther in time and contrast early republican Rome or, in
Greece itself, Sparta with Periclean Athens. For as we come down the stream of Time
in its present curve of evolution, humanity in the mass, carrying in it its
past collective experience, becomes more and more complex and the old distinct
types do not recur or recur precariously and with difficulty. Its limitations at once appear, when we look back at its prominent examples. Early Rome and Sparta were barren of Page – 89 thought, art, poetry, literature, the larger mental
life, all the amenity and pleasure. of human existence; their art of life
excluded or discouraged the delight of living. They were distrustful, as the
exclusively ethical man is always distrustful, of free and flexible thought and
the aesthetic impulse. The earlier spirit of republican Rome held at arm’s
length as long as possible the Greek influences that invaded her, closed the
schools of the Greek teachers, banished the philosophers, and her most typical
minds looked upon the Greek language as a peril and Greek culture as an
abomination: she felt instinctively the arrival at her gates of an enemy,
divined a hostile and destructive force fatal to her principle of living.
Sparta, though a Hellenic city, admitted as almost the sole aesthetic element
of her deliberate ethical training and education a martial music and poetry,
and even then, when she wanted a poet of war, she had to import an Athenian. We
have a curious example of the repercussion of this instinctive distrust even on
a large and aesthetic Athenian mind in the utopian speculations of Plato who
felt himself obliged in his Republic first to censure and then to banish the
poets from his ideal polity. The end of these purely ethical cultures bears witness to their insufficiency. Either they
pass away leaving nothing or little behind them by which the future can be
attracted and satisfied, as Sparta passed, or they collapse in a revolt of the
complex nature of man against an unnatural restriction and repression, as the
early Roman type collapsed into the egoistic and often orgiastic license of
later republican and imperial Rome. The human mind needs to think, feel, enjoy,
expand; expansion is its very nature and restriction is only useful to it in so
far as it helps to steady, guide and strengthen its expansion. It readily
refuses the name of culture to those civilisations or periods, however noble
their aim or even however ‘beautiful in itself their order, which have not
allowed an intelligent freedom of development. Page-90 lopment two distinct periods, one of art and beauty, the
Athens of Phidias and Sophocles, and one of thought, the Athens of the
philosophers. In the first period the sense of beauty and the need of freedom
of life and the enjoyment of life are the determining forces. This Athens
thought, but it thought in the terms of art and poetry, in figures of music and
drama and architecture and sculpture; it delighted in intellectual discussion,
but not so much with any will to arrive at truth as for the pleasure of
thinking and the beauty of ideas. It had its moral order, for with out
that no society can exist, but it had no true ethical impulse or ethical type,
only a conventional and customary morality; and when it thought about ethics,
it tended to express it in the terms of beauty, to kalon, to epieikes, the beautiful, the becoming. Its very
religion was a religion of beauty and an occasion for pleasant ritual and
festivals and for artistic creation, an aesthetic enjoyment touched with a
superficial religious sense. But without character, without some kind of high
or strong discipline there is no enduring power of life. Athens exhausted its
vitality within one wonderful century which left it enervated, will-less,
unable to succeed in the struggle of life, uncreative. It turned indeed for a
time precisely to that which had been lacking to it, the serious pursuit of
truth and the evolution of systems of ethical self-discipline; but it could
only think, it could not successfully practise. The later Hellenic mind and
Athenian centre of culture gave to Rome the great Stoic system of ethical
discipline which saved her in the midst of the orgies of her first imperial
century, but could not itself be stoical in its practice; for to Athens and to
the characteristic temperament of Hellas, this thought was a straining to
something it had not and could not have; it was the opposite of its nature and
not its fulfilment. Page-91 miniscent of the license of imperial Rome. It had
learning and curiosity, but gave very little of itself to high thought and
truth and the more finished achievements of the reason, although it helped to
make free the way for philosophy and science. It so corrupted religion as to
provoke in the ethically minded Teutonic nations the violent revolt of the
Reformation, which, though it vindicated the freedom of the religious mind, was
an insurgence not so much of the reason, – that was left to Science, – but of the moral instinct and its ethical
need. The subsequent prostration and loose weakness of Italy was the inevitable
result of the great defect of its period of fine culture, and it needed for its
revival the new impulse of thought and will and character given to it by
Mazzini. If the ethical impulse is not sufficient by itself for the development
of the human being, yet are will, character, self- discipline; self-mastery
indispensable to that development. They are the backbone of the mental body. Page-92 Ananda,1 - can be thus helped by each other, the one to a richer, the other to a greater self-expression. But that even this much re- conciliation may come about they must be taken up and enlightened by a higher principle which must be capable of understanding and comprehending both equally and of disengaging and combining disinterestedly their purposes and potentialities. That higher principle seems to be provided for us by the human faculty of reason and intelligent will. Our crowning capacity, it would seem to be by right the crowned sovereign of our nature.
1 Tapas is the energising conscious-power of cosmic being by which the world is created, maintained and governed; it includes all concepts of force, will, energy, power, everything dynamic and dynamising. Ananda is the essential nature of bliss of the cosmic consciousness and, in activity, its delight of self-creation and self-experience. Page – 93 |